The Patient as Interpreter of the Analyst's Experience
作者: Irwin Z. Hoffman, Ph / 14619次阅读 时间: 2010年10月02日
来源: Contemp. Psychoanal., 19:389-422 标签: Analyst Experience Interpreter Patient The
www.psychspace.com心理学空间网

^:W)?}#Du:T-H0(1983) Contemp. Psychoanal., 19:389-422心理学空间 j6?]Z BPM!Y
心理学空间Li z.bp B ?C(e
The Patient as Interpreter of the Analyst's Experience
$bVm]i+`g#L!m'RW0心理学空间2P c G2{K%{
Irwin Z. Hoffman, Ph.D.心理学空间T PtT |P6f@

/J'i/Qz}?/B2ew0心理学空间],J1p];Q
Introduction
&X/a5uh,s1tj2I ?#@0
0Z)^z@,c(q:_'O0THIS PAPER PRESENTS A POINT OF VIEW on the psychoanalytic situation and on psychoanalytic
'[6je-j[ u0technique through, in part, a selective review of the literature. An important underlying assumption of the paper is
1E(gnQK t5hh }8Cf]0that existing theoretical models inevitably influence and reflect practice. This is often true even of models that心理学空间wO3A#q/f1Hd
practitioners claim they do not take seriously or literally. Such models may continue to affect practice adversely as心理学空间{5`YWp;a1zY.?
long as their features are not fully appreciated and as long as alternative models are not recognized or integrated.心理学空间HL tth#K-v
An example of such a lingering model is the one in which the therapist is said to function like a blank screen in the心理学空间.nLGS[
psychoanalytic situation.心理学空间-b1Y|ak

4NN.g Bj0The Resilience of the Blank Screen Concept心理学空间^AM2{9_*X
心理学空间!\ r|Z'f|vR
The psychoanalytic literature is replete with attacks on the blank screen concept, the idea that the analyst is not
lE V3_[|!\*]!h*D0accurately perceived by the patient as a real person, but that he serves rather as a screen or mirror to whom various
V0QMEs0attitudes, feelings, and motives can be attributed depending upon the patient's particular neurosis and its心理学空间\ D]%tj$]$p)sR
transference expression. Critiques of this idea have come from within the ranks of classical Freudian analysts, as心理学空间 @ G ~&jz)h*`+q-I
well as from Kleinians and Sullivanians. Even if one looks only at the classical literature, in one way or another, the
G1HL)q ^[Y:s4a0blank screen concept seems to have been pronounced dead and laid to rest many times over the years. In 1950, Ida心理学空间[;Nl"Aya{$D:\
Macalpine, addressing only the implications for the patient's experience of classical psychoanalytic technique as she
D-ePv8ad$N0conceived of it (that is, not considering the analyst's personal contributions), said the following:
:H,F)T}$i4D0心理学空间8Zt;~'bk+`Vg
It can no longer be maintained that the analysand's reactions in analysis occur spontaneously. His behavior is
y4g!|W4wl0a心理学空间Dg#]8E"h~.DG
response to the rigid infantile setting to which he is exposed. This poses many problems for further investigation.心理学空间.Oh#Rn/pX3^
One of them is how does it react upon thepatient? He must know it, consciously or unconsciously (p. 526, italics心理学空间 H;{9W | w2S
added)心理学空间6H-M+J&R bP
.
x(T!V l;nA7Dd0
b'R V5uT'T@{0
$A+P @ h9b:i.u$V*h7@ K0Theresa Benedek said in 1953:心理学空间1ymc1TbU)J4h
心理学空间]~k rG6M8`#iH
As the history of psychoanalysis shows, the discussion of countertransference usually ended in a retreat to defensive心理学空间,cQl,h6G${
positions. The argument to this end used to be (italics added) that the classical attitude affords the best guarantee that心理学空间5BM1~+tO$_
the personality of the therapist (author's italics) would not enter the action-field of the therapeutic process. By that
A;U6}}Ss*o.V9g&h0one assumes that as long as the analyst does not reveal himself as a person, does not answer questions regarding his
3_b4V8N&S0U m1Z y0own personality, he remains unknown as if without individuality, that the transference process may unfold and be心理学空间e$p[mpCZ
motivated only by the patient's resistances. The patient—although he is a sensitive, neurotic individual—is not
E#@#r.gg.\0supposed to sense and discern the therapist as a person (p. 202).心理学空间 x8|-E C b6tt\

-pi#`.]8T0In 1956 Lucia Tower wrote:心理学空间Tg mKZ%@-Ic\C

)m o:B:W'{q~"P0I have for a very long time speculated that in many—perhaps every—intensive analytic treatment there develops心理学空间*i,~QVF+b$qn
心理学空间#NT"N0iH6C
something in the nature of countertransference structures (perhaps even a "neurosis") which are essential
IrV0}O"{0andinevitable counterparts of the transference neurosis (p. 232)心理学空间5zb!a)X6Tl
.心理学空间 Oh7nvF'w9`2]W&g
心理学空间Ll+G:d[ |Tb
心理学空间(mq;s"NJ*^
Copyright . 1983 W. A. W. Institute, New York心理学空间J9O1N)K3|,V:j
20 W. 74th Street, New York, NY 10023心理学空间G@xMi!]p
All rights of reproduction in any form reserved.心理学空间hvr'N5pR L8h
Contemporary Psychoanalysis, Vol. 19, No. 3 (1983)心理学空间+ceaw uDq`
心理学空间"zzx/n jIp%VGS
心理学空间U5X3`"I(\2V6l
In the sixties Loewald (1960), Stone (1961), and Greenson (1965) added their voices to the already large心理学空间!b[&p Sd
chorus of protest against this remarkably resilient concept. From varying theoretical perspectives, the critiques
^ A"L R2tE u(D0continued into the seventies and eighties as represented, for example, in the writings of Gill (1979) ; (1982a) ;心理学空间*{em2|5B ~3\2O,W
(1982b) ; (1983) ; (Gill and Hoffman, 1982a) ; (1982b) ; Sandler (1976) ; (1981) and Kohut (1977), among many心理学空间"eIZ3aZ-x/WMu#b
others. In fact, the blank screen idea is probably not articulated as often or even as well by its proponents as it is by心理学空间w'V/Grn4B.s$O;Nn
its opponents, a situation which leads inevitably to the suspicion that the proponents are straw men and that shooting心理学空间9PAUFx$s
them down has become a kind of popular psychoanalytic sport.1心理学空间2y&U#W1C;^5b
心理学空间~s*v#Q6P0c A
I am persuaded, however, that the issue is a very important one and that it deserves repeated examination and心理学空间o`u?y&A:o
discussion. The blank screen view in psychoanalysis is only one instance of a much broader phenomenon which心理学空间 tmt9O:j,c3x{
might be termed asocial conceptions of the patient's experience in psychotherapy. According to these conceptions,心理学空间B&Z;Sx4vfD
there is a stream of experience going on in the patient which is divorced to a significant extent from the immediate心理学空间n6H%c&IO(_R
impact of the therapist's personal presence. I say "personal presence" because generally certain theoretically
'`7j \eL%x6P7Gk9j0prescribed facilitating aspects of the therapist's conduct are recognized fully as affecting the course of the patient's
(kRf*{osO0experience. But the paradigm is one in which proper or ideal conduct on the part of the therapist allows for a flow心理学空间 m/X6nKi$?G
of experience which has an organic-like momentum of its own and which is free to follow a certain "natural" course.心理学空间*m.k t,w2B&{|
An intriguing example of this asocial paradigm outside of psychoanalysis can be found in client-centered therapy.
"bx-E#YL\0Ideally, the classical client-centered therapist is so totally and literally self-effacing that his personality as such is
qH_8U"{&A F9aM4c/I0effectively removed from the patient's purview. Carl Rogers stated in 1951:
5wY&Pr$@7@#Ip0
]LS0k]u)r8Wf0It is surprising how frequently the client uses the word "impersonal" in describing the therapeutic relationship after the
Ir7F*p Lq0conclusion of therapy. This is obviously not intended to mean that the relationship was cold or disinterested. It心理学空间eB p:E6Y#|n
appears to be the client's attempt to describe this unique experience in which the person of the counselor—the心理学空间$~9RT]xC;So
counselor as an evaluating, reacting person with needs of his own—is so clearly absent. In this sense it is
T"tdw#B$f*w7T0"im"-personal … the whole relationship is composed of the self of the client, the counselor being de-personalized for
Z%y}U5Y-g!HQ0the purposes of therapy into being "the client's other self" (p. 208).心理学空间/J~&H8RXB8if1c

hYT2l!T!}6U0In psychoanalysis, the blank screen idea persists in more or less qualified and more or less openly
#AC?#Ye d t*O:E0acknowledged forms.2 The counterpart of the notion that the analyst functions like a screen is the definition of心理学空间obOt |S!e
transference as a distortion of current reality. As Szasz (1963) has pointed out, this definition of transference can心理学空间$q{J!XI/V
serve a very important defensive function for the analyst. This function may partly account for the persistence of
uQ8g5NJ0the concept. I believe that another factor that has kept it alive has been the confusion of two issues. One has to do
9Q[y2y-bg.I0with the optimal level of spontaneity and personal involvement that the analyst should express in the analytic
d'|^7k$i,t0situation. The other has to do with the kind of credibility that is attributed to the patient's ideas about the analyst's
(y3|*W$W)e"JU0experience. A theorist may repudiate the notion that the analyst should behave in an aloof, impersonal manner
2ArX!HV3o(p0without addressing the question of the tenability of the patient's transference based speculations about the analyst's
Q;E#K!se8I/x0experience. To anticipate what follows, such speculations may touch upon aspects of theanalyst's response to the
e,Jd|O%N@G y0patient which the analyst thinks are well-concealed or of which he himself is unaware. Ingeneral, recommendations
/\1U6`*}9E\0pertaining to the analyst's personal conduct in the analytic situation may very well leaveintact the basic model
?7eG,i@ I6?$N0according to which the transference is understood and interpreted.心理学空间n(F)j&iR#J2b%I
心理学空间f}v:aD7hICUm
1It is interesting that critics of the blank screen concept have frequently been concerned that others would think they were beating a dead
6sAN ^g5VB0si0horse (see, for example, Sterba, 1934, p. 117) ; (Stone, 1961, pp. 18–19) ; (and Kohut, 1977, pp. 253–255).心理学空间.] G fZdOSq W
心理学空间!Fv/R!\-|8F)q
2Dewald's (1972) depiction of his conduct of an analysis exemplifies, as Lipton (1982) has shown, a relatively pure, if implicit, blank screen
k~x"HK0position.
4T V}ud~;d#{B0心理学空间!n cA*F2i
Standard Qualifications of the Blank Screen Concept心理学空间!}q#t uL"t5j)e
心理学空间 k}'p l'|Z w#{k
The notion that ideally the analyst functions like a screen is always qualified in the sense that it applies to only心理学空间la0nt8n!a+P,LV
a part of the patient's total experience of the therapist, the part which is conventionally regarded as neurotic
5EgQT!`$|wKa0transference. This is the aspect of the patient's experience which, allegedly, distorts reality because of the persisting心理学空间u^(X:l7k/h ]0OI
influence of childhood events, wishes, conflicts, and adaptations. There are two kinds of experience which even the
(L/w,M'E9r0staunchest proponents of the screen or mirror function of the analyst recognize as likely to be responsive to心理学空间0C-Y"`8IdG|
something in the analyst's actual behavior rather than as expressions of pure fantasy. One is the patient's perception
-Lg)}/joR&M9YC0of the analyst as essentially trustworthy and competent, a part of the patient's experience which Freud (1912)
{JB5r6luU0subsumed under the rubric of the unobjectionable positive transference but which others, most notably Sterba心理学空间/m/}m^:jg8{F
(1934), Greenson (1965), and Zetzel (1956) have chosen to exclude from the realm of transference, designating it as心理学空间_x+Bm3l
the experience of the working or therapeutic alliance.3 The second is the patient's recognition of and response to心理学空间N-p}*iT_;w
relatively blatant expressions of the therapist's neurotic and antitherapeutic countertransference. Both categories of心理学空间_})nzpA
experience lie outside the realm of transference proper which is where we find the patient's unfounded ideas, his
t/DFN8EvVi;q0neurotic, intrapsychically determined fantasies about the therapist. The point is well represented in the following心理学空间/k~ xY|x'K(V s P7j7r
statements (quoted here in reverse order) which are part of a classical definition of transference (Moore and Fine,心理学空间1D j.ML Jd
1968):心理学空间"V8S5pP4E6e

^ G9PT8wLD6x01.心理学空间d j*J/m!X
Transference should be carefully differentiated from the therapeutic alliance, a conscious aspect of the
oi*K'^2}8~0relationship between analyst and patient. In this, each implicitly agrees and understands their working心理学空间w9@;oVV
together to help the analysand to mature through insight, progressive understanding, and control.
i.I-xD A7iD0v02.
(JaF Zs(OX"f"C0One of the important reasons for the relative anonymity of the analyst during the treatment process is the fact心理学空间!| laj^#DC4kC@
that a lack of information about his real attributes in personal life facilitates a transfer of the patient's revived心理学空间 N9Q3D Z#N;FPZHz5^
early images on to his person. It also lessens the distortion of fantasies from the past by present perceptions. It心理学空间7k7DqBy
must be recognized that there are situations or circumstances where the actual behavior or attitudes of the心理学空间 f1d:VC:blb;|
analyst cause reactions in the patient; these are not considered part of the transference reaction (See心理学空间 qFD1v/l^2f
countertransference) (p. 93).心理学空间 Q'M u-Oq JV
Two Types of Paradigms and Critiques
!z/Ee4I1|p j"_9]0
b5Y%O!D/q O8C0In my view, critiques of the screen concept can be classified into two major categories: conservative critiques
1k}&p#UA$N6s \F j6H-k-B0and radical critiques. Conservative critiques, in effect, always take the following form: they argue that one or both
$| oD A\!lA0of the standard qualifications of the blank screen view noted above have been underemphasized or insufficiently
w!T6y5j8z&U*a0elaborated in terms of their role in the analytic process. I call these critiques conservative because they retain the心理学空间 i F K @}9xH
notion that a crucial aspect of the patient's experience of the therapist has little or no relation to the therapist's actual
a a5F(NC(t g9_,z0behavior or actual attitudes. The conservative critic reserves the term transference for this aspect of the patient's心理学空间-N!j U)E#~
experience. At the same time he objects to a failure to recognize sufficiently the importance of another aspect of the
O:N1b1e(V7t[*N0patient's experience which is influenced by the "real" characteristics of the therapist, whether these real心理学空间+t&YdQ b3MSE
characteristics promote or interfere with an ideal analytic process. The dichotomy between realistic and unrealistic
(M,Qp9Y*K ld&yb0perception may be considered less sharp, but it is nevertheless retained. Although the realistic aspects of the
-F3ZIJ9_ u3^ F*mf \0patient's experience are now given more careful consideration and weight, in relation to transference proper the
#L O2u z cW_0therapist is no less a blank screen than he was before. By not altering the standard paradigm for defining what is or心理学空间9L:Iii_c O
is not realistic in the analytic situation, conservative critiques of the blank screen fallacy always end up perpetuating心理学空间5Z"a/o4d;i;m!yK%P*T f
that very fallacy.心理学空间Md;Z9^ d&D;c-?
心理学空间WjE9k)J:J
3For discussions of the implications of Freud's position on this matter see Lipton (1977a) and Gill (1982, pp. 9–15).
6Y;t3o3g/kCYo0心理学空间QW$^ Z)VrM
In contrast to conservative critiques, radical critiques reject the dichotomy between transference as distortion
XYq:~0Cv^:r+y0and non-transference as reality based. They argue instead that transference itself always has a significant plausible心理学空间"o4]Fm;c8}9~;l|d
basis in the here-and-now. The radical critic of the blank screen model denies that there is any aspect of the patient's心理学空间f/OFXE$mLeU
experience that pertains to the therapist's inner motives that can be unequivocally designated as distorting of reality.心理学空间;K fR2C!i"G(~FJ
Similarly, he denies that there is any aspect of this experience that can be unequivocally designated as faithful to reality.
+eyzTsG0O0The radical critic is a relativist. From his point of view the perspective that the patient brings to bear in interpreting the
:L/q9h)v$d9w0therapist's inner attitudes is regarded as one among many perspectives that are relevant, each of which highlights
7T8Ba&m&B,p|5u0different facets of the analyst's involvement. This amounts to a different paradigm, not simply an elaboration of the心理学空间$HmVqki
standard paradigm which is what the conservative critics propose.心理学空间 _ To%]G @)w

*Wk6u!rA$WI0In rejecting the proposition that transference dominated experience and non-transference dominated experience
'n&b9?HY@a&E;L0can be differentiated on the grounds that the former is represented by fantasy which is divorced from reality心理学空间@w#R5?K Dy6s
whereas the latter is reality based, the radical critic does not imply that the two types of experience cannot be
f5\)OyI|0distinguished. Indeed, having rejected the criterion of distorted versus realistic perception, he is obliged to offer
2A7O7J%ks\o0other criteria according to which this distinction can be made. For the radical critic the distinguishing features of
/C~3gPXOc;k~W0the neurotic transference have to do with the fact that the patient is selectively attentive to certain facets of the
!^9v4JP*u&dm$@ u0therapist's behavior and personality; that he is compelled to choose one set of interpretations rather than others; that
Z`,f)|#\9v0his emotional life and adaptation are unconsciously governed by and governing of the particular viewpoint he has
E Q)Vg!Ke X)d0adopted; and, perhaps most importantly, that he has behaved in such a way as to actually elicit overt and covert
ETo7cZ/U5d0responses that are consistent with his viewpoint and expectations. The transference represents a way not only of心理学空间B8M tG8jXL9c
construing but also of constructing or shaping interpersonal relations in general and the relationship with the analyst
O-p|8hzSo0in particular. One could retain the term "distortion" only if it is defined in terms of the sense of necessity that the
QFM-X'Vo0patient attaches to what he makes happen and to what he sees as happening between himself and the analyst.
pwR r [DZ:h0
\it4c$pM S0The radical critiques are opposed not merely to the blank screen idea but to any model that suggests that the心理学空间2OPq]1cd$c;v%nb+a
"objective" or "real" impact of the therapist is equivalent to what he intends or to what he thinks his overt behavior
:k/r9Rpb2c0has conveyed or betrayed. What the radical critic refuses to do is to consign the patient's ideas about the analyst's
)i|P*Q.Q9W%UH5F0hidden motives and attitudes to the realm of unfounded fantasy whenever those ideas depart from the analyst's心理学空间Vuaa8cA+wn
judgment of his own intentions. In this respect, whether the analyst's manifest conduct is cold or warm or even心理学空间/ua.o&A]"\a(wK
self-disclosing is not the issue. What matters to the radical critic in determining whether a particular model is心理学空间&} A5m,uy` U
based on an asocial or truly social conception of the patient's experience is whether the patient is considered capable
*R x[ Q\8N0of understanding, if only preconsciously, that there is more to the therapist's experience than what meets the eye,
.R-O c;VB ^0even more than what meets the mind's eye of the therapist at any given moment. More than challenging the blank
@8rCAlZd1}0screen fallacy, the radical critic challenges what might be termed the naive patient fallacy, the notion that the
'SP dr-q0patient, insofar as he is rational, takes the analyst's behavior at face value even while his own is continually
!T0eZ4I D"iTw+V/t0scrutinized for the most subtle indications of unspoken or unconscious meanings.
"{'\{H+G*y0心理学空间u{&p'G u J0k$[o2c
Although we now have a broad range of literature that embraces some kind of interactive view of the
;P{2a6ryV0psychoanalytic situation (Ehrenberg, 1982), emphasis upon interaction per se does not guarantee that any particular
[0FdTV s0theoretical statement or position qualifies as one which views the transference in relativistic-social terms.心理学空间IU$@&W ] ^@
Moreover, emphasis on interaction can obscure the fact that a particular theorist is holding fast, for the most part, to
,E3i;AW4pe0the traditional view of neurotic transference as a distortion of a given and ascertainable external reality.心理学空间0q6f2Tny+p jm

www.psychspace.com心理学空间网
TAG: Analyst Experience Interpreter Patient The
«精神分析发展心理学 精神分析
《精神分析》
《释梦》及其意义»